Home Artists Posts Import Register

Content

If I focus really hard do my power of quantum mechanics allow me to manifest reality? No, but then why did some of the founders of the theory seem to think that consciousness and quantum mechanics were inextricably linked. 

The behavior of the quantum world is beyond weird. Objects being in multiple places at once, communicating faster than light, or simultaneously experiencing multiple entire timelines ... that then talk to each other. The rules governing the tiny quantum world of atoms and photons seem alien. And yet we have a set of rules that give us incredible power in predicting the behavior of quantum system - rules encapsulated in the mathematics of quantum mechanics. Despite its stunning success, we’re now nearly a century past the foundation of quantum mechanics and physicists are still debating how to interpret its equations and the weirdness they represent.

It’s not surprising that the profound weirdness of the quantum world has inspired some outlandish explanations - nor that these have strayed into the realm of what we might call mysticism. One particularly pervasive notion is the idea that consciousness can directly influence quantum systems - and so influence reality. Today we’re going to see where this idea comes from, and whether quantum theory really supports it.

To start, we need to go back to one of the earliest interpretations of quantum mechanics - the Copenhagen interpretation, often associated with Neils Bohr and Werner Heisenberg. It tells us that the very act of measurement or observation causes an experiment to settle on a particular result, and that it’s meaningless to talk about a well-defined objective reality before that measurement is made. Let’s see where this kooky idea comes from - using the classic example is the double-slit experiment. A single electron is shot at a pair of slits, passes through, and is registered on a detector screen on the other side. When multiple electrons are shot one after the other, they form a series of bands. That’s the same pattern that would be produced by a wave passing through both slits - a so-called interference pattern. But that’s weird because this interference pattern seems to guide the path of each electron independently of the others. Each solitary electron must know the entire wave pattern - which means it must, in some sense, travel through both slits.

The Copenhagen interpretation explains the result of this experiment by saying that the electron does NOT travel as a particle or as a physical wave along one of these paths. Instead it travels as an abstract “probability wave” - something we call a wavefunction. That probability wave defines the location of the electron at any point IF you try to measure it. The Copenhagen interpretation states that, prior to measurement, it’s meaningless to talk about a real, physical state for the electron. It exists only as the possible outcome of a future measurement. Prior to measurement, it IS its wavefunction.

Copenhagen tells us that when we make that measurement the wavefunction “collapses” - it goes from a cloud of possible final destinations for the electron to a more or less definite spot on the detector. Wavefunction collapse seems essential because our large-scale, classical world isn’t made of probability clouds, it’s made of objects with clearly definable properties. When does the quantum transition to the classical?

Let’s look at the process in the case of the double-slit experiment. The electron wavefunction passes through both slits, reaches the electronic detector, and then excites a second electron somewhere on the detector. That second electron begins a cascade - an electrical impulse that travels along circuits to be registered by a computer, which updates an image on the computer screen to show where the electron hit. And that information travels via photons to light-sensitive molecules in our retina, which initiate electrical signals to our visual cortex, and more electrical signals in other parts of our brain result in a subjective sense of the original photon’s chosen destination on the screen.

We call this chain of information between the detector and the mind the von Neumann chain, after the great Hungarian-American physicist John von Neumann. He wrote that wavefunction collapse must happen somewhere between the measuring apparatus and the conscious awareness of the result of that measurement. But exactly where? Probably not as soon as our electron wavefunction reaches the detector. The first electron to become excited in the detector is also a quantum object. That means the traveling electron’s wavefunction will just become mixed with the wavefunctions of all electrons that it could possibly energize. We should get what we call a superposition of states: a wavefunction in which an electron at every location on the detector screen is simultaneously excited and not excited.

So perhaps the wavefunction transition happens somewhere in the circuitry, or in the computer, or in the retina. But all of these things are made of atoms - the “von Neumann chain” from detector to mind is a chain of quantum objects. With no clear boundary between the quantum and the classical, where does the collapse of the wavefunction happen? We call this open question the Measurement Problem.

John von Neumann believed that wavefunction collapse must happen at the moment of conscious awareness of the result of an experiment. Another of the greats of early quantum theory agreed with him. Eugene Wigner was a fellow Hungarian-American, and actually went to school with von Neumann before they both ended up at Princeton. The idea that consciousness collapses the wavefunction is now called the von Neumann-Wigner interpretation, and it’s sort of a subset of the Copenhagen interpretation.

In 1961, Wigner devised a thought experiment to argue for the role of consciousness. The Wigner’s friend experiment goes something like this: suppose you don’t conduct the double-slit experiment - your friend does. You know the experiment has been completed with a single photon reaching the detector, and your friend is aware of the result, but you are not. So we have an extra step to our von Neumann chain - before it the information about this quantum experiment reaches your conscious awareness, it has to pass through your friend’s conscious awareness.

So we have this weird moment - somewhere between the landing of that photon on the screen and your friend telling you the result. From your perspective, your friend’s entire brain exists in a quantum superposition of all possible results of the experiment. Only after your friend tells you the result of the experiment does their brain-wavefunction collapse to a single experimental outcome. So you ask your friend - what was it like for your whole brain to be in a superposition of states? They think you’re crazy - they tell you the wavefunction collapsed as soon as the physical experiment was completed. But there was no way for that collapse to have happened from your perspective - no information had reached you. So there’s a conflict - different observers say the wavefunction collapses at different times.

Eugene Wigner felt that this conflict meant that it was impossible for entire brains - or more importantly - conscious experiences generated by those brains - to be in superpositions of states. Therefore he concluded that conscious experience itself must play a role in generating wavefunction collapse.

Wigner and von Neumann weren’t the only ones who questioned the relationship between the mind and the Measurement Problem. Wolfgang Pauli was perhaps the first to assert the connection, and his influence may have started the development of the Copenhagen interpretation - later attributed mostly to Bohr and Heisenberg. Bohr himself was careful about claiming any direct role of the conscious mind - and vigorously defended himself after Einstein accused him of introducing mysticism into science. But Heisenberg was more open to mystical interpretations and the direct influence of consciousness, at least early on. Even Erwin Schrodinger, in his 1958 lectures Mind and Matter states that consciousness is needed to make physical reality meaningful.

With the greats of quantum physics inclined to speak in mystical terms, it’s not surprising that these ideas stuck around. In the 1970s, books like The Tao of Physics and The Dancing Wu Li Masters drew parallels between eastern mystical traditions and quantum physics - which on its surface seems like a nice idea - poetic descriptions of the mysteries of physics with philosophical musings.

But these works really opened the floodgates. Self-help books and documentaries proliferated making all sorts of claims - like that you can influence reality by acts of will - collapse the wavefunction in your favour to force the location of a spot on a screen, or influence the shapes of snowflakes, or get a promotion. Then there’s the idea that external reality doesn’t have an objective existence - our minds invent the universe. But as Richard Feynman said, "If you think you understand quantum mechanics, you don't understand quantum mechanics." The more you know about this theory, the less likely you are to pretend you fully understand its deepest implications. And yet the most confident claims about quantum mechanics seem to be the mystical ones. They tend to be made by people who have never studied the theory deeply, but nonetheless have great surety in cherry-picking and misinterpreting the early speculations of some of its founders.

Those founders did question the role of consciousness and the connection between subjective and objective reality - and they were right to do so. The weird behavior of quantum world demanded the courageous and open-minded speculation that characterizes a great scientist. But the other quality of a great scientist is openness to changing your mind. And most of them DID change their minds - veering away from the idea of a direct, causal role of consciousness. In Heisenberg’s later writing he states that the wavefunction collapse must be a continuous process between measurement device and conscious mind - and definitely not a sudden event caused by the latter. Wigner too - he switched camps and spoke against the notion of the primary role of consciousness. He denied what he called the solipsistic view: that the mind is foremost, that consciousness generates the universe.

In fact we can use Wigner’s friend to put to rest the worst misinterpretations of the Copenhagen interpretation. This time you stand next to your friend and you perform the double slit experiment together. A single electron reaches the detector screen and you both learn its location at the same time. You talk to each other and agree that you observed the same result - the wavefunction collapsed in the same way for both of you. So then ... if the conscious mind causes the collapse - who caused it, you or your friend? If you both have the power to initiate that collapse, why will you always agree on the result, no matter how many friends observe the result. So, what ... maybe one observer is forcing their prefered wavefunction collapse on everyone else. Or maybe you’re the only observer and you’re inventing your friend and, well, the rest of reality and there are no other observers in the universe to give conflicting results. No, the only coherent explanation for the consistency of experimental results between different observers seems to be that the result of the experiment - and reality - exists independently of individual observers. Sure, you could talk about a global consciousness collapsing a universal wavefunction - but that’s not going to give you any powers of quantum wishing.

Despite not having settled the Measurement Problem - at least not with full consensus, modern quantum theory has come a very, very long way since its foundation. In fact there’s are some very precise explanations for why the wavefunction appears to collapse. And conscious observation may play a role - but not in the way you might think. To understand that we need to understand what happens to these multiple alternate histories after the electron wavefunction reaches the detector - and why these histories stop communicating with each other. We need to learn about quantum decoherence and the quantum multiverse. For now, one thing I can say with certainty that your own future wavefunction includes a deeper dive into the quantum-classical divide, on an upcoming episode of Space Time.

Comments

Anonymous

Thanks for illuminating the darkened past. You didn't offer an explanation for the 1.7 second difference in arrival time between gravitational waves and EM waves. Were the EM waves just slower than the gravitational waves or were they generated 1.7 seconds after the gravitational waves? Then, why?